Nashville Great Books Discussion Group
A reader's group devoted to the discussion of meaningful books.
Saturday, January 31, 2015
In the Prologue Zarathustra proclaimed that God is
dead. What does he mean by that? In this section Zarathustra gives a series of
speeches to elaborate on his message. If
God is now dead, what happened? How did
this idea of God begin in the first place?
Zarathustra explains: “This god whom I created was man-made and madness,
like all gods! Man he was, and only a
poor specimen of man and ego: out of my own ashes and fire this ghost came to
me, and, verily, it did not come to me from beyond. What happened my brothers? I overcame myself.” Zarathustra believes God is a creation of our
own imaginations. The idea of God is
merely a projection of our own wish to have more power and life. God does not, as the Bible says, show himself
to us from some otherworldly realm. The
idea of God begins within the minds of weak people.
In Zarathustra’s opinion we need to be strong and face
reality as it is, not as we wish it to be.
There is no God. There is no
heaven. Then why do so many people
believe in them? Zarathustra has an
answer: “It was suffering and incapacity that created all afterworlds… this
created all god and afterworlds…” Since
our bodies are frail and mortal we try to find comfort wherever we can. Religion provides comfort. But in Zarathustra’s opinion it’s a false
comfort. We try to escape bodily pain
and death through some sort of existence based on a (non-existent) spirit or
soul apart from the body. So Zarathustra
thinks we’re searching in all the wrong places.
When we try to escape pain and suffering we go wrong. He says, “It was the body that despaired of
the body… it was the body that despaired of the earth.” Zarathustra wants us to overcome despairing life
in a body.
But it takes a strong and healthy person to overcome this
kind of despair. Life as Zarathustra
envisions it is not for weaklings. Only
the strong survive and society is full of weak, sick people. He says, “It was the sick and decaying who
despised body and earth and invented the heavenly realm…” Only sick and decaying people dream of
heaven. And they have infected many
others with their own despairing attitudes: “Many sick people have always been
among the poetizers and God-cravers… they always look backward toward the dark
ages.” Nietzsche thinks religious-minded
people are messed up mentally. After
all, they’re chasing after fantasies.
How healthy can that be?
In some ways this story is similar to our reading in The Gospel of
Mark. Jesus had disciples and so does
Zarathustra. Jesus teaches in parables
and so does Zarathustra. Jesus wants to
guide us to a new way of living and so does Zarathustra. But there’s a fork in the road concerning
this new way of life. The message in The
Gospel of Mark is our souls, as well as our bodies, need to be healed. Nietzsche is having none of that. He doesn’t believe we have souls so they
don’t need to be healed. The way he puts
it, “‘Body am I, and soul,’ thus speaks the child... But the awakened and knowing say: body am I
entirely, and nothing else…” The Gospel
of Mark says almost the exact opposite: “Jesus…said
unto them, Suffer the little children to come unto me, and forbid them not: for
of such is the kingdom
of God. Verily I
say unto you, Whosoever shall not receive the kingdom of God
as a little child, he shall not enter therein.” Jesus and Zarathustra have very different
ideas about the nature of the body, the soul, heaven and children. So it’s not surprising that Jesus would see
God as a Father in heaven and Zarathustra would see him as man-made madness.
Saturday, January 24, 2015
NIETZSCHE: Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Prologue & Aristotle’s Vision)
Friedrich Nietzsche is most famous for one short phrase: “God is
dead.” Besides that, what
else does he have to say? Flaubert
spoke by telling a story and Hume spoke through philosophy and reason. Nietzsche does both. In Thus Spoke Zarathustra he tells a
story with a philosophical flavor. Zarathustra
is an unusual man. He’s
what Nietzsche calls an “overman” or what we might call a super-man. Zarathustra’s not like us. He’s stronger than we are and smarter
too. He went up into the
mountains for ten years to meditate and then one morning he woke up and it
literally dawned on him: “I am weary of my wisdom.” What wisdom had he discovered after
many years of meditation? He
discovered that society’s values are worthless. The things people say they admire and
respect are worthless. Using
Zarathustra’s own words, what does he think of Happiness? “It is poverty and filth and wretched
contentment.” Reason? “It is poverty and filth and wretched
contentment.” Virtue? “…poverty and filth and wretched
contentment.”
Nietzsche knew this would not be a popular message. In the story he writes, “Behold, I
teach you the overman…” And
what was the result”? “When
Zarathustra (Nietzsche) had spoken thus… all the people laughed…” This was predictable. Before anyone had ever read the story
Nietzsche had already built in his response: “They do not understand me.” Why not? It may be because he’s just plain hard
to understand; the story is difficult. But
Nietzsche also suspected people wouldn’t want to hear what he had to say. And he was right. Most people like comfort; Zarathustra
(Nietzsche) has only contempt for bourgeois comfort: “We have invented happiness,
say the last men, and they blink. They
have left the regions where it is hard to live, for one needs warmth. One still loves one’s neighbor and
rubs against him, for one needs warmth.” He thinks this need for neighbors and
warmth makes us weak; it keeps us from becoming super-men. We huddle together for comfort and
soon “Everybody wants the same, everybody is the same.”
What is an ordinary person supposed to
make of all this? As
Nietzsche says, “Dark is the night, dark are Zarathustra’s ways.” He’s right. What do we have in common with a
super-man who thinks happiness is only “poverty and filth and wretched
contentment?” Aristotle
agrees with Nietzsche that everybody wants to be happy. But he thinks everybody wants
happiness for a good reason: happiness is a good thing to have. Reason and virtue are also good things
to have. They’re not
poverty and filth, as Nietzsche says. Reason
and virtue are values that lead us out of poverty and filth. They help us to live better lives. To live better lives we don’t need to
go off to the mountains and meditate. We
need to settle down and live with our neighbors. This is not a weakness. It’s what human beings were made to do. A man who lives outside a social
network is either a beast or a god. Aristotle
thinks it’s beastly to live outside of society; Zarathustra thinks it’s
god-like. Since “God is
dead” Nietzsche thinks we need new super-men to become new gods and create new
values. “To lure many away
from the herd” is Nietzsche’s goal. For
Aristotle this is not good. Man
is a social being. At his
core Man is a political being, a creature whose natural habitat is the polis,
or city. Even Nietzsche
admits “companions I need, living ones.” What he objects to is the herd
mentality of values. He
wants to create new values and recruit new Zarathustras to join him. This message appeals to many college
students. That’s why
Aristotle says young people aren’t prepared to study politics. Building society is hard work and
needs the very values Nietzsche rejects.
Monday, January 19, 2015
What Good is Philosophy?
It would be a wonderful thing
if philosophy could give us clear and unambiguous answers to all the questions
we have about ourselves and the world in which we live. But this is not the way
it works. Philosophy cannot give us those clear and indisputable answers
because the human mind itself is incapable of providing us that information.
Why not? What's the problem? Well, the problem, as Descartes demonstrated, is
that the human mind is incapable of giving us absolute certainty about anything
because every thought which the mind can hold is capable of being doubted. It
is a curious property of human intelligence that our mind generates questions
about all of the mental objects (ideas) which we hold, and at the same time,
will generate doubts or questions regarding the reliability of those ideas. In
other words, the mind both generates and negates the ideas we have. Everything
which can be doubted is subject to that peculiar quality of being both real
("true") and unreal ("false"). The only fact which
Descartes found which cannot be doubted is our own existence. We are not even
sure what the "our" part of that statement refers to. Our own identity
is contingent upon other facts which need the support of external proof. This
is the essential problem of philosophy: to separate what we know for certain
from what we do not know for certain. And it turns out that there is damn
little information (or "facts") that we know for certain. Hume did
not invent this situation; he merely commented upon it.
As Hume says, the
"self" which we take for granted is nothing more than a bundle of perceptions in the mind. We'd like to believe that something substantial is
behind human consciousness, but when we examine it closely we can't find
anything but a bundle of nerves which convey electrical impulses from one part
of the brain to another. We are thinking machines. But is that all we are? Does
human consciousness completely disappear when the electricity is turned off.
This is one of those deep questions that only theologians and philosophers
worry about. It is disturbing to think that human consciousness is nothing but
a program running inside the brain (computer) in our heads.
What about soul? Does
anything endure or survive our biological death? Are we composed of just matter
or is there something else (soul, spirit, mystical energy)? Science today is
incapable of answering that question with the tools at its disposal. But
philosophy doesn't require the same body of evidence as does science. It is
perfectly ok to speculate about what might be possible or what might be true. Philosophy
has an entire branch of metaphysics devoted to the art of speculation, as does
theology. The only rule that philosophy observes is that one should be entirely
rational and honest in one's adventures of the mind. In other words, you should
not be guided by emotions or prejudice in your quest for knowledge. The only
thing that Descartes believed could not be doubted was our own mind. Hume
refers to this "mind" as a bundle of perceptions. As a result of his
own epistemological journey, Descartes provided us with one basic rule for exploring
the unknown: everything (but our own existence) should be open to doubt.
Saturday, January 17, 2015
HUME: Of Personal Identity (What Would Socrates Think?)
Of Personal Identity is a chapter from Hume’s book entitled
A Treatise of Human Nature. Hume has an interesting theory. He believes “mankind… is nothing but a bundle
or collection of different perceptions.”
Human beings are made up of sense perceptions and our ideas come from
those perceptions. We are what we see
and touch. In Hume’s view “the mind is a
kind of theatre” where we watch one thought after another come in and out of
view. This would get confusing if we stopped
to think about it. Most of us don’t. But Hume did.
He wondered how we can make sense of all this confusion of perceptions
and thought. How can we identify all
these diverse perceptions as ideas? What
makes them related to other ideas? Hume
concludes, “Our chief business, then, must be to prove, that all objects, to
which we ascribe identity, without observing their invariableness and
uninterruptedness, are such as consist of a succession of related objects.”
There’s the key term: identity. Things change. Plants grow.
People get old. They don’t look
anything like they did before. And yet
in our minds they still seem like the same things they were. Why?
Hume gives an example. He says, “in
a very few years both vegetables and animals endure a total change, yet we
still attribute identity to them.” An
acorn grows into an oak tree. Acorns and
oaks don’t look anything alike. And yet
in our minds the IDENTITY of the acorn and the oak tree is the same thing. That acorn became this oak. An even stranger example is a church. Let’s say a church (call it St. Michael’s) burns
down and is rebuilt in a new style with different materials. But we still call it St. Michael’s. Why? Hume
says “…neither the form nor materials are the same, nor is there anything
common to the two objects but their RELATION to the inhabitants of the parish;
and yet this alone is sufficient to make us denominate them the same.”
Hume says the “church” still exists but only in our
minds. There’s a real building made of
stone, that’s true. And before that
there was a real building made of wood.
But now they’re entirely different buildings made of entirely different
materials. St. Michael’s Church still
exists in our minds but only because our memories connect the current stone
building with the wooden building that stood there before. In reality they don’t have the same
“identity” because they’re nothing like they were. They’ve totally changed. To call them the same thing is a mental
delusion. And it’s not just acorns and
churches. The same principle applies to us too.
Hume says “The identity which we ascribe to the mind of man is only a
fictitious one…” My mind, my own
identity, is a fiction?
This all sounds very strange. Everything Hume says sounds perfectly logical. But really, what good is it? Hume started off his essay by saying “there
are some philosophers who imagine we are at every moment intimately conscious
of what we call our ‘self’… (Footnote: not just philosophers; every sane person
thinks they have a self.) …nor is there anything of which we can be certain if
we doubt of this.” That’s what “some
philosophers” think. And that’s the whole
point. If I can’t be certain that “I” even
exist then what else in the whole wide world can I ever be certain of? Hume seems to be undermining the foundations
of our minds. Is this what philosophy is
for? Socrates had a sort of maxim that
it was good to Know Thyself. Hume
implies there’s no self to know. Is this
what philosophy has come to in the past two thousand years? It’s too bad Socrates and Hume can’t sit down
together and have a long talk.
Saturday, January 10, 2015
FLAUBERT: A Simple Heart (Felicite and Her Bird)
Felicite never understood Church dogma. She didn’t even try. She loved going to church and attended daily Mass. But Felicite would fall asleep when they
tried to teach her dogmas like the Trinity.
“She found it (particularly) hard to visualize the Holy Ghost; for he
was not only a bird, but a flame as well, and at other times a breath.” Felicite isn’t alone. Much ink has been spilled by scholars trying
to explain the Trinity. Sharper minds
than Felicite’s have failed to grasp this great mystery of Church dogma.
The bird. As the years
passed Felicite grew older and the years were not kind to her. She knew the deep tragedy of losing both her
beloved nephew Victor and Madame Aubain’s daughter Virginie. And Felicite never married. “Years passed, one like another, and
uneventful except for the recurrence of Holy Days.” Then one day joy came into her life in the
form of a bird. There’s an old story
about a little girl who was as confused about the Holy Spirit as Felicite was;
instead of saying “the Holy Spirit, the Paraclete” this girl would always say
“the Holy Spirit, the parakeet.”
Felicite’s bird wasn’t a parakeet.
It was a parrot. And this wasn’t
just any old parrot. It was Loulou. Felicite threw her whole heart and soul into
that bird. Strangers couldn’t understand
her devotion. “They would say he looked
like a turkey, or even like a chunk of wood; comparisons that cut Felicite to
the heart.” Felicite had no parents, no
husband or children, and no close friends.
She only had Madame Aubain and Loulou.
In the end she had many bad memories; “her wretched childhood, the
disillusionment of her first love, her nephew’s going away, and Virginie’s
death.” Felicite’s room became a kind of
museum or shrine; a reflection and memorial of everything she had loved and
lost in her long life. Then she became
deaf and “her small circle of ideas shrank even more.”
The vision. As the
poet (W.B. Yeats) says, things fall apart, the center cannot hold. And so it was with Felicite. Physically she was falling apart. Eventually she became not only deaf but blind
too. Under these circumstances “without
sorrow, rather brimming over with peace, she would remember how things used to
be.” Today we would say she retreated
into a shell and maybe even suffered from clinical depression. On the outside it appeared that way. “Having no communication with anyone, she
lived in a kind of sleepwalker’s trance.”
And yet her interior life was still rich and satisfying. It was just in a quirky kind of way. She saw things according to her own
interpretation. Felicite reasoned, “It
would not have been a dove the Our Heavenly Father had picked to be the bearer
of His Word. Nobody ever heard a dove
talk; it must have been an ancestor of Loulou’s.” Is this the reasoning of a devout 19th
century Catholic heart? Or is it just
plain old apostasy? Had Felicite’s faith
blossomed with personal heartfelt devotion?
Or had she reverted to the ancient practice of worshipping creatures
instead of the Creator? At the end of
her life a strange thing happened: “with her last breath there appeared to her,
while the heavens opened, a gigantic parrot, hovering directly over her
head.”
Was it really the Holy Ghost? Or was it just a figment of Felicite’s
overworked imagination? Flaubert doesn’t
say. It’s up to the reader to decide. That’s what makes A Simple Heart a great
story worthy to be included in The Great Books Series. Flaubert never preaches. He paints a picture with words: a gigantic
parrot hovering over a woman looks either hilarious or scary; unless you’ve
read the story of Felicite and Loulou.
Monday, January 05, 2015
FLAUBERT: A Simple Heart (Felicite and Faust)
John Stuart Mill once said “It is better to
be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to
be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.” It’s a famous quote and makes a good sound
bite for philosophy class. But is that
really a fair choice? If we take out
“dissatisfied” and “satisfied” as adjectives we have the following
choices. Would we rather be a human
being or a pig; Socrates or a fool? Seriously. A better question we might throw back at Mill
would be this: Would he rather be Faust or Felicite? Is it better to be a dissatisfied, immoral genius-poet;
or a moral and satisfied illiterate peasant girl?
It may be going a little too far to call
Faust an immoral man. And it may be a
bit of a stretch to say Felicite was happy with her life. But an objective comparison might be
helpful. What criteria can we use to
objectively examine and compare two lives?
In one of the Great Books readings John Dewey takes the traditional Virtues
as his criteria: Justice, Wisdom, Courage and Moderation. How would Faust and Felicite compare?
Justice.
Faust was a doctor and the son of a doctor. He had a fine education and lived in
luxurious comfort. And yet he complained
about the human condition in general and his circumstances in particular. He was directly or indirectly responsible for
four deaths; Gretchen, their baby, Gretchen’s mother and her brother. Felicite was an illiterate orphan peasant
girl. She was sent out to work tending
cows “as a mere infant” and made her way through life as best she could. She started with nothing. But she worked hard and never
complained. And she was good to
people. Give one point to Felicite.
Wisdom.
As smart as he was Faust had no problem dealing with
Mephistopheles. Is it wise to make a
deal with the devil? And he also got his
girlfriend pregnant out of wedlock. How
much wisdom does that take? Felicite had
no “book learning” but at least she knew how to keep from getting
pregnant. She also knew how to head off
unwanted advances, run an efficient household, and handle drunken uncles. Felicite leads 2-0.
Courage.
When the chips were down Faust had a chance to show his courage in a
prison cell with Gretchen. But when the
chips were down he ran away. When the
Aubain family was threatened by a rampaging bull Felicite could have run
too. But she didn’t. When the chips were down Felicite held her
ground. So it’s Felicite three Faust
zero.
Moderation.
Part of Faust’s problem was he wanted to go to extreme limits of human
experience. That’s what prompted his
deal with Mephistopheles; Faust wanted to go beyond normal human emotions. The most extreme emotion Felicite felt in her
young life was a broken heart; just a normal broken heart. And she did what normal people do. She grieved for awhile; then got on with a
normal life. It’s a shutout. Felicite wins 4-0.
Maybe we can’t score life like we score a baseball
game. But there’s one more area where we
can see the difference between them.
Faust had mastered theology. But
he was bored and cynical about religion.
Felicite? “Of dogma she
understood nothing; did not even try to understand.” She couldn’t read but she listened
intently. “Felicite saw the Garden, the
Flood, the Tower
of Babel, cities all in
flames, dying nations; idols overthrown; and these idols left her awed by the
Almighty and fearful of His wrath. She
wept when she heard the story of the Passion.
…Sowings, harvests, winepresses, all the everyday things the Gospel speaks
of, had their place in her own life; God, by His passage, had sanctified
them…” Felicite had a simple heart and a
simple mind. But Faust clearly missed
all this in his studies. In baseball
Felicite would be ahead 5-0.