Thoughts on Justice
Are happiness and justice incompatible? Well, that depends a lot on how you define
"happiness" and what kind of "justice" you have in mind. For
most Americans, our ideas about justice are rooted in the Old Testament in
which every injury or personal insult must be avenged. The idea of revenge was
originally tied to the community's belief in divine law. The law which bound
the community together came directly from the authority of God. Thus, justice,
which is rooted in divine law, required that law breakers be punished. Over
time, tribal laws became linked with a conception of justice derived from a
belief in natural law. It was natural because it applied to every person in the
world which itself was created by God.
In this way, the laws of the city are derived from the laws
of the tribe, which were derived, in turn, from God whose laws governed all human
behavior. Yet, prior to the growth of cities, the moral code of human behavior
was known as the "eye for an eye, and a tooth for a tooth" school of
punishment. Thus, morality became linked to personal injury along with the need
for revenge. Over time, the human desire for revenge became indistinguishable from our idea of justice,
which in turn became linked with one's idea of honor. Honor (or respect) is
historically a form of public esteem., while the opposite of honor is shame.
Shame is analogous to ridicule or loss of social status. Thus, when Job loses
all his possessions and children, he becomes a man without honor. Yet his honor
is restored when God favors him with new wealth. But a blinded Oedipus is
compelled to leave Thebes and live out his days in disgrace.
In almost all ancient societies, cowardice was considered dishonorable,
and so was lying and thievery. A man's word was his bond. For the Greeks in
Homer, the idea of honor was directly linked to the idea of respect. Honor in
battle required that a man be willing to die for his king (or his country). Honor
also requires that personal insults be revenged. Otherwise, one would lose respect. Honor
requires that Hector fight Achilles, even though he knows he cannot win. Respect
and honor are thus intertwined on the battlefield. In normal life, respect generally
takes two forms: self-respect, and public (or social) respect. The difference
between self-respect and public honor is tied to the idea of reputation. When
Aaron Burr kills Alexander Hamilton in a duel, their conflict is over a
perceived insult to Burr's honor. Any public display of disrespect will always
be perceived as a loss of reputation. This is what justifies revenge, and revenge
is the most common means by which one's reputation is restored. Honor compels
Orestes to murder Clytemnestra in revenge for his father's death. His duty to
his father compels him to act. Yet his revenge against his mother invokes a
kind of divine retribution. The Furies descend upon Orestes to avenge his
mother's death. So where is justice in this chain of murder and revenge?
At some point in the development of cities, it becomes
necessary to ban public dueling. The
idea of honor is now subordinate to the idea of public safety. And so the
criminal justice system, with its courts and juries, becomes the arbiter of all
personal disputes.
However, when it comes to disputes between nations, war
remains the most frequent means of settling these disputes. It is not until the
establishment of the United Nations will there be any other means of resolving
these kinds of disagreements. After all, diplomacy is a rational enterprise and
men rarely act rationally when honor is at stake. Patriotism, which is the form
national honor takes, remains a vestige of the classical idea of honor.
With the Nuremberg trials of 1945, the principle of crimes
against humanity becomes the moral equivalent to crimes against the state, and the
violation of the immutable laws of God. The principles of justice on which the Nuremberg
trials were conducted bring us back to the ancient principles which guided men
in a tribal culture. Once again, natural law becomes the foundation for
our contemporary understanding of justice. This
is what Socrates, in his inquiry into the principles of justice, is trying to
establish-- a rational ground for the belief in the idea (and the possibility) of
something which lies beyond our reach (what Lincoln called "the better
angels of our nature." In other
words, bringing the immutable law of a divine order down to the level of ordinary
fallible human beings.
0 Comments:
Post a Comment
<< Home