Nashville Great Books Discussion Group
A reader's group devoted to the discussion of meaningful books.
Tuesday, November 29, 2016
In
last week’s reading Sophocles showed us why we sometimes have an obligation to
disobey unjust laws. (Antigone, GB1)
Antigone chose to disobey a law she believed was unjust in order to obey
a higher law. This week we find Socrates
arguing the opposite point of view in Plato’s dialog on Crito. Socrates (via Plato) says we should normally obey
the laws, even if we think some of them are unjust. Of course there are crucial differences
between Sophocles’ Antigone and Plato’s Socrates. Antigone was a young woman; Socrates was an
old man. Not all young women think we
should disobey laws we don’t like. Not
all old men think we should obey them anyway, even if many people think the
conviction was unjust in the first place and even if we’re sentenced to death. But Socrates thinks “it would scarcely be
appropriate in a man of my age to be distressed if he now had to die.” He’s not too concerned about getting the
death penalty. He says “If it so pleases
the gods, let it be so.” Not all old men
are that wise or that calm in the face of death. King Lear (GB5) is a good example. Shakespeare shows his tragic downfall and by
the end of the play Lear laments: “Pray, do not mock me: I am a very foolish
fond old man, Fourscore and upward, not an hour more nor less; And, to deal
plainly, I fear I am not in my perfect mind.”
There’s nothing wrong with Socrates’ mind. Because of his long apprenticeship in
philosophy he seems sharper at seventy than he was in his prime and Socrates ultimately
decides to reject Crito’s advice to escape. He decides to stay in prison and take his
medicine (the hemlock poison which was the Greek form of capital punishment at
that time).
Crito tries to
persuade Socrates that it’s perfectly reasonable to disobey an unjust law and makes
three good arguments for him to escape from prison. He knows Socrates can’t be swayed by
emotional pleas. We’ve already seen that
in Socrates’ trial in the Apology (GB1).
Only the truth will persuade Socrates.
So Crito points out three major obligations Socrates should consider. Obligation 1: the obligation to one’s
self. Underneath Crito’s argument lies
one foundational belief: the trial was a sham.
Everyone knows it, even those who voted to convict Socrates. No one would be surprised if Socrates walked
away from the injustice of a false conviction.
That way he could continue his philosophical speculations in the safety
of, say, Thessaly. Since that argument
didn’t work Crito goes to plan B.
Obligation 2: your friends. Rather
than appealing to Socrates’ own self-interest Crito asks him to consider his
friends. Crito says, in effect, think
about us: “People won’t believe that you refused to escape even though we were
eager to help.” The truth is, people
will think that we abandoned you when we should have stood by you. Antigone didn’t abandon her brother, even in
death, and we don’t want people to think we abandoned you. Socrates doesn’t buy this argument. He replies: “Why should we be concerned about
what people will think? Those worth
considering will believe that things happened as they did.” Crito tries one more argument, kind of a
philosophical Hail Mary attempt. He
tells Socrates “You betray yourself when you could be saved” and you won’t
escape for the benefit of us, your friends so consider Obligation 3: your
family: “… in addition, I think you’re betraying your sons… Either a man
shouldn’t have children, or he should accept the burden of raising and
educating them.” Crito’s main point is
this. Socrates has put the interests of
philosophy ahead of everything else; his family, his friends, his own best
interests. Crito is asking Socrates to
consider being a little more pragmatic.
Don’t be so stubborn and dogmatic about abstract philosophical
principles. Compromise. Live to fight another day. By staying and facing execution you’re only justifying
the actions of “the many” and you yourself said “they cannot make a man wise or
foolish. They only act at random.” Why let a random act of violence stop your
pursuit of wisdom? Your obligation right
now is to fight injustice by disobeying bad laws.
Tuesday, November 22, 2016
SOPHOCLES: Antigone (Creon and the Preacher)
In
his book on Ethics (GB1) Aristotle made the famous statement that “Happiness is
an activity of the soul in accordance with virtue.” Happiness is something we do, not something
we feel. After reading Antigone we may
want to ask if the same observation applies to wisdom as well. Is wisdom an “activity of the soul” and something
we do; or is wisdom a kind of comprehensive understanding of the world by the
mind? Creon apparently believed wisdom
is something we do. He was decisive in
ordering the body of Eteocles to be honored while the body of Polyneices would
be left without burial. The result? Toward the end of the play Creon laments
“Whatever my hands have touched has come to nothing. Fate has brought all my pride to a thought of
dust.” He tried to do what (we have to
assume) he thought was the right thing to do given the unique circumstances he
faced as king of Thebes. The Preacher
from the book of Ecclesiastes (GB5) understood Creon’s predicament better than
most of us. The Preacher was a king too;
the king of Israel. And the Preacher’s
conclusion was much the same as Creon’s.
The Preacher asks “What profit hath a man of all his labour which he
taketh under the sun?” What good did it
do you, Creon, to become king of Thebes?
It brought you wealth and power.
Did it bring happiness too?
No. Did it give you wisdom? Maybe.
Just not the clear and optimistic wisdom of Aristotle.
The wisdom Creon
stumbled upon was more of the melancholy variety. It was the sad wisdom of experience. He thought he was doing the right thing. But so did Antigone. This wasn’t a situation where there were good
guys on one side and bad guys on the other.
They both had convincing arguments that they were doing the right
thing. It was a tangled situation and
would not have surprised the Preacher.
He had pretty much seen it all before and famously stated that there was
nothing new under the sun: “I have seen all the works that are done under the
sun; and behold, all is vanity and vexation of spirit. That which is crooked
cannot be made straight…” Creon thought
it was the king’s job to make crooked things straight. Maybe he was right. But the Preacher learned from experience that
there are some things in this world that can’t be made straight; at least not by
men. Only God (or the gods) can
straighten them out. Even king Creon finally
had to admit that “the laws of the gods are mighty, and a man must serve them
to the last day of his life!” The
Preacher agreed: “Let us hear the conclusion of the whole matter: Fear God, and
keep his commandments: for this is the whole duty of man.” The Preacher learned patience the hard way
and came to understand that “To every thing there is a season, and a time to
every purpose under heaven.” There’s a
time to do this, a time to do that, and a time not to do anything at all but
just sit and ponder the problem of fate, much the same way Job (GB4) sat and
pondered the problem of fate with his friends.
There’s not much time to meditate for a man who has the responsibilities
of a king. Ordinary folks can take more
time to ponder what the Messenger in the play has to say: “Fate raises up, and
Fate casts down the happy and unhappy alike: no man can foretell his Fate.” Or meditate on the advice of the Chorus when
they sing “There is no happiness where there is no wisdom; no wisdom but in
submission to the gods.” The Preacher (and
king of Israel) somehow found time to ponder these things. What did he decide? “Then said I in my heart, As it happeneth to
the fool, so it happeneth to me; and why was I then more wise?” If fate raises up and casts down both the
wise and the foolish then what advantage does wisdom have over
foolishness? And even if I want to seek
out wisdom anyway, how do I go about finding it? Creon and the Preacher agree we can’t find it
by reading books. The Preacher put it
this way: “of making many books there is no end; and much study is a weariness
of the flesh.” Of course the great irony
is this. We find the wisdom of Creon and
the Preacher by reading about them in a book.
Monday, November 14, 2016
SOPHOCLES: Antigone (Freedom or Fate)
Every
four years Americans vote for President of the United States. American democracy has a long tradition of a
smooth and peaceful transition of power as the outgoing President hands on the
office to the incoming President-Elect. Not
every democracy makes a peaceful transition. In this play Sophocles shows what happens
when the transition of power is not peaceful.
The political plot is simple. The
“presidential” term is up for Eteocles and now it’s time to hand power on to
the next ruler, Polyneices. But Eteocles
refuses to step down. So Polyneices goes
away, raises an army and comes back to Thebes to try and take the office by
force. In the ensuing battle both
leaders are killed. Then Creon steps in
to take charge and tries to restore law and order to Thebes. With that background in mind we should
remember what Simmel had to say about freedom.
His theory of freedom is that it evolves historically from slavery to
serfdom to freedom. Money liberates
individuals by freeing them from personal obligations to specific individuals. With money I’m free to choose my own destiny. Sophocles doesn’t agree.
Money
gives us the illusion that we’re free to choose our own destinies. For Sophocles the concept of Fate is much
more prominent than we think. We like to
think more money will give us more freedom but what it actually does is corrupt
hearts that may otherwise be honest. Creon
puts it like this: “Money! There’s
nothing in the world as demoralizing as money.
Down go your cities, homes gone, men gone, honest hearts corrupted,
crookedness of all kinds, and all for money!”
Money is just a symptom of a deeper problem and Sophocles wants us to
ponder the tragedy of the human condition.
Every character in this play tries to do what is right. Creon’s position is entirely logical. “Polyneices made war on his country. Eteocles defended it.” Therefore Polyneices is a traitor; Eteocles
is a hero. Creon tries to do the right
thing and clearly explains his position: “No ruler can expect complete loyalty
from his subjects until he has been tested in office. Nevertheless, I say to you at the very outset
that I have nothing but contempt for the kind of Governor who is afraid, for
whatever reason, to follow the course that he knows is best for the State; and
as for the man who sets private friendship above the public welfare, I have no
use for him.” Antigone and Ismene also
want to do the right thing. Antigone
tells Ismene “now you can prove who you are.
A true sister, or a traitor to your family.” Ismene is afraid and her position is
pragmatic. She says “The law is strong,
we must give in to the law in this thing, and in worse. I beg the Dead to forgive me, but I am
helpless: I must yield to those in authority.”
But it’s not just fear that motivates her opinion. She also considers her religious and civic duties. When Antigone says “Apparently the laws of the
gods mean nothing to you” Ismene responds “They mean a great deal to me; but I
have no strength to break laws that were made for the public good.” Ismene has a point. Antigone is acting on what she conceives to
be her private obligation. Creon is
acting on what he conceives to be best for the public good. Ismene is caught in between. Creon’s son Haemon puts this whole situation
into perspective when he says “Reason is God’s crowning gift to man, and you
are right to warn me against losing mine… yet there are other men who can
reason too; and their opinions might be helpful. You are not in a position to know everything…” Haemon is right too. No one knows everything. We each have our own opinions and we live
amidst a turmoil of clashing human opinion; but when the dust finally settles,
what then? Sophocles sums it up in one
word: Fate. “Fate raises up, and Fate casts down the happy and the unhappy
alike: no man can foretell his Fate.” We
may really want to do the right thing but love of money and power get all mixed
up in politics. The result of that
potent mixture is what Sophocles calls Fate.
Simmel thinks people in the rational modern world are free to choose
their own destinies; Sophocles hints that we’re not as free as we think.
Monday, November 07, 2016
SIMMEL: Individual Freedom (The Psychology of Freedom)
In
last week’s reading Georg Simmel made his case that an economy based on
monetary transactions allows for maximum individual freedom. Money gives us many more choices about how we
earn a living, where we live, and what we do with our leisure time. Exchanging money for goods and services make
us more dependent on the system but less dependent on individual people. There’s both an upside and a downside to this
kind of economic arrangement. Here’s an
example of what Simmel is talking about.
He says “the personality as a mere holder of a function or position is
just as irrelevant as that of a guest in a hotel room.” The upside of this arrangement is the
depersonalization of business transactions.
A waitress at a restaurant or a clerk at a convenience store won’t
refuse me service just because they don’t like me. The downside of this arrangement is the
depersonalization of business transactions.
Under a monetary system I’m just another customer and as irrelevant as “a
guest in a hotel room.”
Not
everyone is comfortable with this kind of arrangement. Tocqueville once remarked that “I know of no
country in which there is so little independence of mind and freedom of
discussion as in America.” He’s talking
about the power of the majority but the principle also holds true for a people
utterly dependent on commerce. In order
to conduct business Americans are compelled to act, and even think, in certain
ways. For Tocqueville being dependent on
such a system is in reality a limitation of freedom. Simmel doesn’t agree. Simmel thinks “we are compensated for the
great quantity of our dependencies by the indifference toward respective
persons and by our liberty to change them at will.” If I don’t like my boss I can find another
job. If I don’t like my neighbors I can
move. Money gives me freedom to change
my relationships to other people. I can
make my own choices about who I do business with and for Simmel “this is the
most favorable situation for bringing about inner independence, the feeling of
individual self-sufficiency.” Simmel
points out that “the vassal could change his master whereas the serf was
unalterably tied to the same one. This
reflects an incomparably higher measure of independence for the vassal compared
with the serf… It is not the bond as such, but being bound to a particular
individual master that represents the real antipode of freedom.”
Simmel
and Tocqueville seem to have a fundamental disagreement about what freedom
means. They both emphasize the psychological
as well as the financial component of freedom.
But Simmel says “The slave could not change his master even if he had
been willing to risk much worse living conditions, whereas the industrial
worker can do that at any time.” Knowing
we can choose to change our circumstances is the key to freedom for
Simmel. That doesn’t necessarily mean we’ll
be better off, at least financially.
Simmel admits that “there is no necessary connection between liberty and
increased well-being.” But there’s a line
from an old George Strait song that goes “I ain’t got a dime but what I got is
mine; I ain’t rich, but Lord I’m free.” That
may be true but Tocqueville counters with this argument. “Fetters and headsmen were the coarse
instruments which tyranny formerly employed; the civilization of our age has
refined the arts of despotism… in democratic republics the body is left free
but the soul is enslaved.” I’m free to
leave my job and work for someone else or I can start my own business. But I’m
still dependent on the same system.
Simmel thinks freedom means not being “bound to a particular individual
master.” Tocqueville worries about something
much worse. Being bound to majority opinion
and having many anonymous masters is a worse fate than having a particular
individual master. Better to deal with the
devil you know than the many devils you don’t know. This is the psychological tension Freud spoke
about in Civilization and Its Discontents (GB1).
Tuesday, November 01, 2016
SIMMEL: Individual Freedom (Economic Freedom)
In
last week’s reading we saw how personal freedoms could easily be smothered by
The Power of the Majority (GB1). Tocqueville
believed that within democracies public opinion and social shaming are stronger
weapons than written laws to enforce uniformity of manners and ideas. In this week’s reading Georg Simmel looks at
the idea of individual freedom but takes that idea in a different direction. For Tocqueville freedom is the ability to
think and act independently. Simmel agrees,
but only up to a point. It’s true that freedom
is the ability to think and act independently but for Simmel freedom can only
exist within an existing framework of social duties. Only social obligations can provide a context
for true freedom and we don’t get more freedom by shirking those obligations. Simmel puts it this way: “what we regard as
freedom is often in fact only a change of obligations; as a new obligation
replaces one we have borne hitherto, we sense above all that the old burden has
been removed. Because we are free from
it, we seem at first to be completely free; until the new duty makes its weight
felt.” If I stop paying rent on my
apartment I seem to be free of the duty to make monthly payments. At least for a while. Before long though I’ll be burdened with the
new duty of finding another place to live.
Simmel
wants us to think more clearly about the relationship between freedoms and
obligations. For him freedom isn’t an
emotional feeling but an objective reality.
He says “moral philosophy always identifies ethical freedom with those
obligations imposed by an ideal or social imperative or by one’s own ego.” We can’t act as moral agents unless we can
choose to fulfill our social obligations in our own way, without coercion. Simmel’s insight is this. We can’t have ethical freedom without a
certain amount of economic freedom.
For
Simmel economic freedom takes three main forms and has followed a clear
historical development. The first phase
is slavery. Under this economic system “the
obligation does not involve a service that is objectively defined, but to the
person himself who performs the service.”
Under modern conditions this would include people such as domestic
servants and military personnel. Their
personal freedoms are constrained by their economic status and their social
obligations are primarily toward a superior authority. The next phase is serfdom. Under this economic system the services of a
serf are generally defined by obligations of time or specified commodities. An obligation of time would be to work at the
manor on a public project two days a month.
But instead of working on public projects the serf may be given another
option. For example “instead of a fixed
amount of labor time and energy, a specific product of labor is required.” The obligation of supplying commodities would
be to turn in a certain amount of corn or wheat each year, for example. This isn’t an ideal situation but it’s a step
up from complete slavery. And it’s not
just under serfdom that this arrangement can be found. “One finds a similar phenomenon today when
talented people, who work for a wage, prefer to work for a company with its
strictly objective organization rather than for an individual employer. They may prefer factory work to service with
people of authority, where they are in a better position financially but feel themselves
less free in subordination to individual personalities.” The third phase of economic freedom is the replacement
of payment in kind (commodities) by money payment. Simmel calls this the “magna charta of
personal freedom” because it gives maximum choice to the individual. It’s a step up from serfdom because “The lord
of a manor who demands beer or chickens or honey from a serf thereby determines
the activity of the serf in a certain direction. But the moment he imposes merely a money
payment the serf is free, insofar as he can decide for himself whether to keep
bees or cattle or anything else.” We’re
still under the social obligation to pay taxes, rent and other expenses but we’re
free to decide how we get the money.